The Solution of the Paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise

Giuseppe Gori
10 min readMar 2, 2019

By Giuseppe Gori.

In this article I explain Zeno’s paradox of Achilles and the tortoise first proposed by Zeno almost twenty five centuries ago. I show what it means to solve a paradox, I propose an explanation of this paradox, and I show why other explanations of this paradox proposed by notable philosophers and mathematicians during the last twenty three hundred years were unsatisfactory.

The History

The paradox of Achilles and the tortoise (one of a set of similar paradoxes) was first introduced by Zeno, a Greek philosopher that lived in the South of Italy approximately 490–450 BC.

According to the procedure proposed by Zeno, Achilles will never reach the tortoise, as every time Achilles reaches the point where the tortoise was, the tortoise has moved further ahead.

The paradox is described, for example, at: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zeno%27s_paradoxes

This is not a difficult problem to solve, and it is easy to calculate the time it will take for Achilles to reach the tortoise. However, by following Zeno’s reasoning the problem seems unsolvable. Thus we have a paradox: two different results for the same problem, depending on which procedure we use.

The paradox has remained unexplained until now.

From the same Wikipedia source we can learn about some of the proposed explanations:

  • Aristotle (384 BC−322 BC) remarked that as the distance decreases, the time needed to cover those distances also decreases, so that the time needed also becomes increasingly small.
    Aristotle also distinguished “things infinite in respect of divisibility” (such as a unit of space that can be mentally divided into ever smaller units while remaining spatially the same) from things (or distances) that are infinite in extension (“with respect to their extremities”).
  • Before 212 BC, Archimedes had developed a method to derive a finite answer for the sum of infinitely many terms that get progressively smaller. Modern calculus achieves the same result, using more rigorous methods. These methods allow the construction of solutions based on the conditions stipulated by Zeno, i.e.the amount of time taken at each step is geometrically decreasing.
  • The ideas of Planck length and Planck time in modern physics place a limit on the measurement of time and space, if not on time and space themselves.
  • According to Hermann Weyl, the assumption that space is made of finite and discrete units is subject to a further problem, given by the “tile argument” or “distance function problem”
  • Infinite processes remained theoretically troublesome in mathematics until the late 19th century.
    While mathematics can calculate where and when the moving Achilles will overtake the Tortoise of Zeno’s paradox, philosophers such as Brown and Moorcroft claim that mathematics does not address the central point in Zeno’s argument, and that solving the mathematical issues does not solve every issue the paradoxes raise.
  • Debate continues on the question of whether or not Zeno’s paradoxes have been resolved. In The History of Mathematics: An Introduction (2010) Burton writes, “Although Zeno’s argument confounded his contemporaries, a satisfactory explanation incorporates a now-familiar idea, the notion of a ‘convergent infinite series.’ “.
  • Bertrand Russell offered a “solution” to the paradoxes based on the work of Georg Cantor, but Brown concludes “Given the history of ‘final resolutions’, from Aristotle onwards, it’s probably foolhardy to think we’ve reached the end.

From: https://plus.maths.org/content/mathematical-mysteries-zenos-paradoxes (A mathematics magazine):

  • “So Zeno’s paradoxes still challenge our understanding of space and time, and these ancient arguments have surprising resonance with some of the most modern concepts in science.”

From: https://www.jstor.org/stable/20833062?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents:

  • “In his Lectures on the History of Philosophy (first delivered in 1805–6) Hegel said that “Zeno’s dialectic of matter has not been refuted to the present day: even now we have not got beyond it, and the matter is left in uncertainty.”
  • Bertrand Russell, in his “Recent work in the Philosophy of Mathematics”, written in l90l, held that “From him [i.e. Zeno] to our own day, the finest intellects of each generation in turn attacked the problems, but achieved, broadly speaking, nothing.”
    Russell, however, thought that the problems involved in Zeno’s paradoxes, which he identified as “the problems of the infinitesimal, the infinite, and continuity”, have not merely been advanced by the mathematicians of his own age but have been completely solved.
  • Some philosophers, notable among them Bergson, refused right from the beginning to accept the newly-advanced theories of continuity and infinity and the consequent definition of motion, and endeavored to offer alternative definitions of motion, continuity and infinity. Since the mathematical solution found a number of champions, including no less able an advocate than Russell, and there was no dearth of the defenders of the philosophic tradition, there ensued a battle royal which brought to the fore scores of re-interpretations of the paradoxes and as many ‘solutions’.
  • No solution, however, was found to be tenable, and soon philosophers despaired of finding a solution that would be acceptable to all.
  • In the 1950s, Prof. Ryle, in offering a solution of the Achilles-Tortoise paradox, feared that the fate of his solution would be, like that of his predecessors’ solutions, “demonstrable failure”, and, Prof. Lazerowitz went to the extent of opining that the paradoxes are (valid) theorems of some metaphysical wish-fulfillment language.
  • The position as it then obtained, (that is, philosophers and mathematicians inability to overtake Zeno) was ably summed up by Prof. Owen in his masterly paper of 1957–58.
  • Many a solution has appeared since then, including one by Shamsi, the author of the artice, but none succeeds in resolving the paradoxes as a whole.”

What Does Solving a Paradox Mean?

As mentioned at the beginning of this article, a paradox proposes the existence of two different results as a solution for the same problem. These results are inconsistent with each other, depending on which procedure is used. Only one can be correct.

As Brown and Moorcroft suggest, we are not looking for a mathematical demonstration that Achilles reaches the tortoise. Assuming they are both running in the same direction, we know he will. We can calculate the exact time, given the distance between the two and the two speeds, using a simple formula:

t = distance/(difference in velocity)

Instead, explaining or invalidating a paradox is to show a fault in the paradox formulation, or the proposed solving procedure, so that we can exclude this procedure and demonstrate that there is only one result for the original problem.

The solution of a paradox is the answer to the question: “How does the paradox formulation (method, or procedure for solving the problem), misrepresent reality or logic?”. That is, we need to show why Zeno’s proposed procedure for solving the problem is conceptually wrong.

Solving a paradox, invalidates its formulation, or the procedure proposed by the author of the paradox and leaves us with only valid procedures for solving the original problem. You can read: “Solving a Paradox, What does it Mean?” at: https://bit.ly/2IudnVO

Why were the previous proposed solutions of Zeno’s paradox not satisfactory?

Most, if not all, the proposed solutions to Zeno’s paradox assume that Zeno’s proposed procedure is correct. The procedure seems to be logical when it is first introduced to us, but we will see that the procedure proposed by Zeno is conceptually incorrect.

The authors then used a procedure similar to Zeno’s faulty procedure to reach the expected correct result for the original problem.

For example, the simple way mentioned earlier to solve the problem (not the paradox) can be examined using a spreadsheet.

Given the assumptions in the diagram below, the time for Achilles to reach the tortoise is 5 seconds:

39 m / 7.8 m/s = 5 s

A simple mathematical solution for the problem

If we calculate a sum of an infinite series, as several mathematicians have suggested, we obtain the same result: Achilles will reach the tortoise.

By applying any legitimate mathematical solution to the problem, we state, in another way that: We can prove that Achilles reaches the tortoise.

What is the problem then?

We know that Zeno is wrong: The fact that his procedure never ends, does not imply that Achilles will not reach the tortoise. We can prove this mathematically in many ways.

Intuitively we all agree with the mathematicians. However, when mentally following the proposed repetitive procedure, the paradox puzzles our mind.

What are the facts?

1. Asserting that Zeno’s procedure never ends is correct, as we can prove it by writing a recursive computer program that follows Zeno’s steps. The program will never end, and never will provide us with the expected result, because the condition for the end of the recursion process (Achilles reaches the tortoise) would never occur.

2. Asserting that Achilles never reaches the tortoise is wrong, as we can prove that he does, by using several mathematical procedures.

Thus, we must conclude that Zeno’s procedure to solve the problem, is not correct.

The question then is: Why is Zeno’s procedure wrong? The key word in the previous assertions is “never”. Never implies time and the problem must be considered in the context of space and time.

Other scientists have shown that a paradox arises when a problem has not been completely specified, and more than one solution to the problem seems to be intuitive, or rational.

Zeno could not completely specify the problem, because the concept of a system of reference was not clear at the time. Most people even today are not intuitively aware of their implicit choice of a system of reference when solving problems related to motion.

Today we know more about the relative motion of two bodies. Solving a problem that involves space and time, requires a defined frame of reference, which cannot be changed without the proper conversions.

The concept of a frame of reference (or reference system), in elementary physics is founded on Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity, First Postulate: All velocities are measured relative to some frame of reference.

The Explanation of Zeno’s Paradox

Zeno’s proposition invites the solver to do a series of steps each time changing the frame of reference:

STEP 1: The starting frame of reference: The point where Achilles starts the race and the tortoise is well ahead,

STEP 2: After a while, we are then asked to use a new frame of reference: The point where Achilles reached and where the tortoise initially started, with the the tortoise now a bit further ahead,

STEP 3: Then again we are asked to use, recursively, a new frame of reference with the new starting point for Achilles and with the tortoise still further ahead, …

With every step we are asked to freeze the process and then continue by re-creating and examining the original problem using a different frame of reference.

After Zeno’s proposed first step, or first change of frame of reference, the problem, as presented in the second step, is exactly the same as the original, the only change being a difference in “scale”. No progress was achieved in solving the problem.

Changing frame of reference essentially restarts the problem-solving procedure.

This realization implies that the problem is never going to reach a conclusion as the step by step procedure is reiterated.

If the frame of reference is changed at every step, our working spacetime shrinks with every step, the solution becomes elusive and the tortoise becomes apparently unreachable.

Zeno proposes a procedure that never ends, for solving a problem that has a trivial solution.

The Solution of the Paradox: (Why Zeno’s proposed procedure is incorrect)

Our solution of Zeno’s paradox can be summarized by the following statement:

Zeno proposes observing the race only up to a certain point using a frame of reference, and then he asks us to stop and restart observing the race using a different frame of reference. This implies that the problem is now equivalent to the original, and necessarily implies that the proposed procedure for solving the problem will never end.

That is, we cannot change frame of reference in the middle of a problem involving velocity, space and time, whether the frame of reference is openly stated (E.g., a point on the surface of the Earth), or implied.

As an analogy, you cannot solve a problem involving measurements by using English Imperial measures at the start of calculations and then switch to metric measures (without proper conversions) in the middle of calculations.

Zeno’s trick works, and puzzles our mind, because we are used to assume one frame of reference when solving this type of problems.

An example

The following is not a “solution” of the paradox, but an example showing the difference it makes, when we solve the problem without changing the frame of reference.

In this example, the problem is formulated as closely as possible to Zeno’s formulation.

Zeno would agree that Achilles makes longer steps than the tortoise.

Let’s assume that one Achilles-step is about 20 tortoise-steps long, and let’s also assume that both Achilles and the tortoise make the same number of steps in the same amount of time. For example, two steps per second (the exact amount doesn’t really matter).

If the tortoise starts the race 20 Achilles-steps ahead of him, then after 20 steps Achilles reaches where the tortoise was (See diagram below: Tortoise starting point).

In the meantime, the tortoise has made 20 of her steps, and she is now one full Achilles-step ahead of him.

We have not changed our frame of reference. We referred to both starting points. These did not move relatively to each other. We could choose any fixed ground point. To please Zeno, let’s continue by referring to the tortoise starting point, where Achilles currently is.

When both runners make one more step, step 21, the tortoise will have moved by one of her steps and she will still be ahead of Achilles by that one tortoise-step. Achilles is now one Achilles-step ahead of the tortoise starting point.

Now, let’s continue, without changing the frame of reference. This is the key point.

We do not redefine the problem and use the current positions of the runners as new starting points, as Zeno proposes, but we refer to the information about the race we have already accumulated in our knowledge base.

Steps must refer to a defined reference point

Achilles then completes his 22nd step, and he is two Achilles-steps ahead of the tortoise starting point. The tortoise will have completed her 22nd tortoise-step from her starting point. Hence the tortoise is now behind Achilles by 18 tortoise-steps.

Thus, if we do not change the frame of reference, the paradox does not appear.

The Dichotomy paradox

In another similar paradox, the Dichotomy paradox, Zeno uses the same argument to paradoxically state that we cannot go from point A to point B, because it would take an infinite number of steps and we would never arrive. In this case as well, we can show that the proposed method involves changing the frame of reference in the middle of the proposed procedure. Thus the proposed method for solving the problem is invalid.

--

--

Giuseppe Gori

CEO, Gorbyte, is currently developing a stochastic distributed crypto-network, GNodes, which will provide free financial transactions to anyone in the world.